Saturday 28 Jun 2014 comment? Since I was a teenager, lightbulbs sold in the USA have listed wattage (power consumed) and lumens (light produced) on the package. Even though most consumers don't know what a lumen is, the numbers can be compared and you can buy the more efficient bulb if you're so inclined. A lightbulb's efficiency can also be expressed as a percentage: a unitless number, immediately comprehensible—but unheard of on lightbulb packaging or in most discussions of the relative merits of, say, incandescents and fluorescents. A cynic might say that bulb packages don't quote efficiency percentages because they're embarrasingly low (wanna guess how efficient an incandescent bulb is?). But to be fair, lumens take the color-dependent sensitivity of the eye into account and thus tell you something that an efficiency percentage doesn't. In a trivial sense, every electrical device is 100% efficient. Any energy consumed comes out in one form or another. Question is, how much of the energy consumed goes toward the desired purpose and how much comes out in an undesired form (usually heat). To gauge efficiency as a percentage, the desired output must be expressible in terms of energy. That's straightforward for a lightbulb (photons embody energy) or a motor (mechanical energy is easily calculated). But what about, say, a computer? Computers throw off a lot of heat—some more than others, making it tempting to deem one computer more efficient than another. But the desired work of a computer is calculation; how to measure that in terms of energy? Is there a theoretical minimum amount of energy needed to add two numbers? The answer is deliciously strange. Calculation inherently takes energy to the extent that the result throws away some of the information embodied in the input. If a circuit adds two numbers and outputs only the sum, the output contains less information that the input. If the sum is 19, you have lost the distinction between having been asked to add 17+2 or 0+19. Writing a bit to a computer memory discards whatever value the memory previously contained and thus can't be done without expending energy. The theoretical minimum cost of changing one bit is k T ln 2, where k is the Boltzmann constant (about 1.38×10-23 joules per degree Kelvin), T is the temperature of the circuit (Kelvin, natch) and ln 2 is the natural log of 2. Real-world computers use much much more than that. Although the mininum energy inherent in calculation has some theoretical interest, there isn't much sense in expressing computer efficiency as a percentage. But back to lighting. Y'all took a guess as to how efficient a lightbulb is, yes? A typical 100W incandescent generates about two watts of light, for an efficiency of about 2%. Thursday 19 Jun 2014 1 comment Nine days ago, I somewhat flippantly wrote I haven't spelled out the reasons I deem free will to be illusory; the proof is left to the reader as an exercise.Consider the arrow of time. Six years ago, I wrote (not flippantly) With only a few exceptions (not believed to be relevant to the point of this discussion),1 interactions between subatomic particles are time-reversible. Macroscopic processes are anything but: water doesn't flow uphill, shards of exploded capacitors don't reassemble themselves, and the hair on my head doesn't get thicker.If the apparent difference between past and future is not inherent in the processes underlying our actions, the familiar notion of the future as night-and-day different from the past starts to look suspect. I realize this may come across as preposterous. Causality, agency, and volition are part of everyday life. We all try to influence the future, but hardly anyone tries to change past events.2 Everything is interrelated. Or—as 4 out of 5 mystics prefer to put it—all is one. Counterfactual conditionals like If I had left home earlier I wouldn't have missed the train are, strictly speaking, nonsense. My having left home when I did is an integral part of the past. Imagining that it were independent of everything else that happened is pure fiction: a practical fiction, but fiction nonetheless. The future might be just as integrated with the past as parts of the past are with each other. If the past is settled and the future is not, with events switching over from up‑in‑the‑air to cast‑in‑stone as the cutting edge of now passes by, note that the angle of that edge is relative. Einstein showed that whether A happens before B can depend on the observer. What is past and what is future depends not just on when you ask but also on who you ask.3 Copernicus helped disabuse humanity of the notion that the Earth held a central, privileged position. The idea that now has a privileged position in time might be just as arbitrary, not that I can imagine how it would feel to fully appreciate that. Happy nineteenth, everyone.
Wednesday 11 Jun 2014 1 comment ![]() Rules often control only the character of patterns, leaving the specifics of each instance to chance. Even identical twins don't have the same fingerprints. All this is a roundabout way of coming to say that we had great cloud patterns yesterday morning. Rather than format a pic to the width of this column, please see a larger version. Tuesday 10 Jun 2014 2 comments
As best I can tell, free will is an illusion: something that isn't what it seems to be. I doubt that quantum indeterminacy has a bearing on free will. We know what kind of systems are sensitive to quantum randomness and which are relatively immune, and there's no indication that neurons are the former. The brain exhibits the flavor of unpredictability by dint of its scale. A network that large can operate 100% deterministically and yet be so chaotic that it bears no resemblance to what we normally think of as mere mechanisms. I haven't spelled out the reasons I deem free will to be illusory; the proof is left to the reader as an exercise. I instead move on to other questions that follow. From Susan Blackmore's 2013 essay Living without free will: But I want to leave aside the complexities of philosophical discussion and turn to a different question — a question that arises for anyone who, like me, rejects the notion of contra‑causal free will — if there is no free will, how should we live our lives?The whole essay is worth reading. It argues that the feeling of having free will is neither inevitable nor necessary for a full, rich, and just life. We make use of 'as if' fictions all the time. Matter is largely empty space, yet I stand on the rung of a ladder as if it were solid. It doesn't feel dishonest to deem the ladder solid for practical purposes. I give Susan Blackmore credit, though, for making the effort to see whether a sense of free will was perhaps optional. But by the end of her essay it's not clear that as if and without are the only two choices. I get more of a sense of transcending the question. Blackmore quotes Alan Watts: We just decide without having the faintest understanding of how we do it. In fact it is neither voluntary nor involuntary. |
current journal
FAQ contact rss/xml atom/xml spam notice archive
|